• Start
  • Previous
  • 9 /
  • Next
  • End
  •  
  • Download HTML
  • Download Word
  • Download PDF
  • visits: 3297 / Download: 2575
Size Size Size
Conception and Assent

Conception and Assent

Author:
Publisher: www.mullasadra.org
English

This book is corrected and edited by Al-Hassanain (p) Institue for Islamic Heritage and Thought

Conception and Assent

Mohammed Taqi Faali

Table of Contents

[Preface] 3

Conception (Tasawwur) 5

Types of conceptions 7

1. The Conception of singular: 7

2. Imperfect compound conceptions: 7

3. The conception of compositional relation: 7

4. The conception of declarative relation: 7

Judgment (hukm) 11

A. Judgment is one of the acts of the soul 11

B. Judgment is a kind of perception rather than act 11

C. Judgment is a revealing act 12

D. Judgment is a conception which is followed by judgment 14

Assent (tasdiq) 17

First View: 17

Second View: 17

Components of a proposition 18

1. Affirmative and negative propositions consist of four components or parts: subject, predicate, judgmental relation, and judgment 18

2. An affirmative proposition has four components 18

3. An affirmative proposition has three parts: subject, predicate, and judgment 19

4. Affirmative and negative propositions have no more than two components 19

Third view: 20

Fourth theory: 21

Notes 25

[Preface]

Knowledge is initially classified into acquired knowledge and knowledge by presence. The acquired knowledge itself is divided into conception (tasawwur ) and assent (tasdiq ).

Regarding the above classification, logicians, theologians, and philosophers have posed a series of extensive discussions which outnumber those related to the first classification of knowledge. Perhaps, the most accurate of all writings concerning this issue is Mulla Sadra’s treatise calledal-Tasawwur wa’l tasdiq (Risalah fi ) (Treatize on Conception and Assent). We can also claim that no one has ever discussed this issue as precisely as Ibn Sina. Our discussion here is mainly a logical one, since both conception and assent are among logical intelligibles, and this is because their qualification is mental, in the sense that their subjects of qualification are in the mind. In other words, what is conceived and what is assented to, or the conceived and the assented (certified), are both in the domain of the mind. The external thing is never qualified by conception or assent unless it enters the mind. Besides, in order to abstract the two notions of conception and assent, a lot of mental considerations and inquiries are necessary. These two issues are not the reflections of the external world to be acquired immediately and without any deliberation. Rather, they appear through mental activities and rational contemplations. Thus the occurrence of two concepts of conception and assent and their qualification is mental; they are among logical secondary intelligibles; and their original place is the field of logic. However, due to some reasons, they were later transferred to other disciplines such as theology and philosophy. Ibn Sina has classified concepts into primary philosophical, and logical ones. He has also made some interesting remarks about the third type.[1]

Different people have defined conception and assent in different ways. In Ibn Sina’s definition,[2] conception has been defined in separation from judgment, and assent has been defined in union with it. Therefore, the main difference between them relates to the presence or absence of a judgment.

In the definition provided by the author ofSharh al-mawaqif ,[3] too, judgment is considered as the criterion for distinguishing conception from assent.

In 'Allamah Hilli’s definition,[4] assent is companied by corresponding, certain, and fixed conditions. Under such conditions, assent is a judgment belonging to the relation between two conceptions - affirmative or negative. Therefore, irrespective of its kind, assent is based on four pillars: judgment, relation, the conception of subject, and the conception of predicate. Such a definition of assent, in fact, corresponds to the definition of proposition. On the contrary, the above-mentioned conditions and pillars are not realized for conception and, thus, it is nothing more than the acquisition of a cognitive form by the mind.

According to the definition provided by Sabziwari,[5] the main distinction between the two lies in the presence of judgment, which is nothing but a mental acknowledgment or confession.

In his definition,[6] 'Allamah tabataba’i maintains that conception has two characteristics. Firstly, it should belong to a single known; and, secondly, there should be no affirmation or negation in it. These two characteristics naturally work in the reverse direction for assent, in the sense that it results from more than a single known and is accompanied by affirmation or negation. Of course, the second characteristic includes the first one, since if a kind of knowledge is accompanied by affirmation or negation, there will inevitably exist more than one known for it. This is because in affirmation something is affirmed for something else, and in negation something is denied to something else.

Consequently, there is no judgment in conception, while it is there in assent, thus the analysis of the nature of the two will not be possible without the study of the content of judgment. At the same time, the effect of judgment on assent needs to be clarified. In this way, there are three key concepts to deal with; namely, conception, assent, and judgment. In what follows, we will try to explain each in detail.

Conception (Tasawwur)

There are four views concerning the problem of conception:

1. Conception can be considered as non-conditioned being as a source of all ontological division. From this point of view, it can be called 'absolute conception’.

2. Conception can be viewed as non-conditioned being as a division.

3. Conception can be regarded as absolute being conditioned by nothing. In this approach, the condition of absence of judgment has been taken into consideration, and the conception is called 'abstract conception’.

4. Conception can be considered as conditioned being as a thing, i.e. as something dependent on judgment.

In the first view, conception is the same as knowledge, rather than a division of it or a divider for assent. In other words, absolute conception is the same mental form that is attained by the knower. Therefore, if we define conception as 'the attainment of the from of something by the mind’, as 'Allamah Hilli says, we have in fact defined knowledge. In this sense, conception is the same as absolute conception, which is synonymous with knowledge. Therefore, it is neither a source of division for assent, nor a division of knowledge.

In the last view, conception is the same as assent, since if it is conditioned by a judgment, it will turn into it. Assent is nothing other than a conception involving a judgment, and, basically, any knowledge which is accompanied by a judgment, whether affirmative or negative, is the same as assent. Therefore, the first and the last views are out of question, and only the other two are taken into consideration. There is of course some disagreement in this regard too, and we must deal with two approaches as follows:

1. A conception which is the source of division for assent must be attained in an absolute and non-conditioned being as a division. In this approach, no condition, whether affirmative or negative, whether conditionedby nothing or conditioned, being as a thing is taken into consideration, and even if there is a condition, it is the very non-conditioned being. Thus neither the presence of judgment nor its absence is considered in it. And this is the very condition for conception; that is, non-conditioned being and absolute. In other words, conception is conditional upon not being accompanied by any condition or limit. Suhrawardi’s words inal-Talwihat could be considered as support for this view.[7]

2. Conception is conditional upon lack of judgment, and it cannot be taken into consideration in an absolute and non-conditioned sense. In this view, the absence of judgment is the condition of conception, and it is considered as being conditioned by nothing. This view belongs to those whom Ghazzali refers to inal-Qistas .[8]

This view has been criticized on the grounds that conception in a way, for example as a condition or a component, takes part in assent; on the other hand, the criterion for assent is judgment. Therefore, how is it possible for conception, which is conditional upon the non-existence of judgment, to be present in an assent, which is conditional upon the presence of judgment? A conception conditioned by the non-existence of judgment is the same as a conception conditioned by the non-existence of assent, and such a conception could not play a part in assent, while the presence of conception in assent is certain. Therefore, it is better to say that with respect to the existence and non-existence of judgment, conception is non-conditioned being; it is neither conditional upon the existence of judgment, so that it would turn into assent, nor is it conditional upon the non-existence of judgment, so that it could not be present in assent. Rather, we must view conception in an absolute and non-conditioned sense, so that it could come together with assent, which is conditional upon judgment. In this way, it can be said that 'conception is the apprehension of the form of the object by the mind, without considering a judgment’. The first part of this definition, the apprehension of the form of the object by the mind, is the same as genus and, thus, includes assent as well. The second part, without considering a judgment, is the same as differentia. Phrasing the differentia in this form is better than stating 'as separated from judgment, since the later suggests the negatively conditioned conception, while the former refers to the same non-conditioned conception. This issue has been clearly explained inSharh hikmat al-ishraq. [9]

In sum, there is no judgment in conception, and it is not conditioned by the existence of judgment; otherwise, it would be the same as assent. Furthermore, the absence of judgment is not a condition or limitation for conception; otherwise, it could not come together with assent, while conception accompanies assent in a way. The only reasonable assumption is that conception is non-conditioned with respect to judgment, and considering the fact that it is so, either as a source of division or division, and that the non-conditioned being as a source of division is the same as knowledge or absolute conception, conception is non-conditioned as a division in relation to judgment. In other words, conception - the production of the form of the object in the mind - is the same as a kind of knowledge in which judgment has been taken into consideration; however, neither the presence nor the absence of judgment is a condition for conception. Rather, with respect to both cases, conception is regarded as absolute and non-conditioned being.

Types of conceptions

As mentioned before, conception is a knowledge that is non-conditioned with respect to judgment. This kind of knowledge consists of the following types:

1. The Conception of singular:

The examples of this type include the conceptions of man, tree, stone, angel, etc. Such conceptions are singular, and there is no combination in them.

2. Imperfect compound conceptions:

The examples here include the combination of a noun and a genitive, a subject and an attribute, a relative pronoun and a relative clause, or any of the two sides of a conditional sentence, provided that each is taken into consideration by itself. In all these cases we are faced with an imperfect combination. The relation resulting from a genitive or attributive combination, or the other two types would be a notional conception - the combination of a conditional clause and the dependent clause is an assent -; however, if any of these clauses is taken into consideration by itself, an imperfect combination will result.

3. The conception of compositional relation:

This kind includes the different types of compositional combinations such as command, prohibition, interrogation, and request. On the other hand, there are declarative combinations. If such combinations are perfect, they will be of the type of assent.

4. The conception of declarative relation:

This conception is conditional upon not being accompanied by an absolute judgment. This is like doubting someone’s standing or the existence of an intelligent creature in Mars. In such cases the judgment is not negative or affirmative, and is, therefore, out of the domain of assent.

As a result, conception is, firstly, more general than absolute conception, thus 'Allamah tabataba’i’s equating conception with the single known is open to criticism. Conceptions could also be present in combinations; therefore, being single or one is not a criterion for conception and cannot distinguish it from assent; however, it could be the distinctive feature of one of the types of conceptions. Secondly, the basis of conception in notional combinations is the absence of judgment. In fact, the only thing that distinguishes such combinations from those related to assent is the presence or absence of judgment. Of course, judgment itself has certain characteristics; for example, whenever there is a judgment, it refers to beyond itself in some way; second, all words come to an end with it; third, it makes the statement either true or false; fourth, all statements expressing a judgment in Persian include the verbast (is). All the above characteristics are among the effects and concomitants of judgment. Therefore, the pivot, the criterion, or the main distinguishing feature here is judgment. And if there is no judgment in some knowledge, there is a conception, either in a compound or a simple form.

From another perspective, conception is divided into universal and particular types. Universal conception is a conception which can be applied to different objects or individuals, such as the concept of book, which can be applied to numerous instances of books. On the other hand, a particular conception is a concept which can only be applied to one individual and has no more than one referent, such as the mental image of Plato. Thus if the concept is such that it cannot be applied to many individuals, it is particular; otherwise, it is universal. Nevertheless, Mulla Sadra and his followers maintain that a concept is always universal as long as it remains a concept, and if thousands of other concepts are added to the first concept, it can still have several referents, since it is a concept. Yet, if we refer to the outside and relate an objective existence to a concept, since existence is individuated, the concept will also be individuated and have a single referent. Accordingly, concept is universal by itself, and the external existence is individuated and personal. In this case, there will be no particular thing, since the mind is always universal and the outside is always individual, unless we consider the particular in the sense of the individual.

Particular conceptions - if they exist at all - have various levels and stages, including sense, imaginal, and estimative conceptions. Rational conceptions are always universal and are themselves divided into primary and secondary intelligibles. The second types itself is sometimes a logical concept and sometimes a philosophical one.

There are different views as to the ways conceptions represent the reality or their verisimilitude:

First view: Some contemporary philosophers consider knowledge, whethertasawwuri (related to conception) ortasdiqi (related to assent), as representing the real world. An essential and indispensable characteristic of knowledge is discovering and representing the reality at all times. If knowledge does not represent what is beyond itself, it is nothing but ignorance. Therefore, conceptions, as a kind of knowledge, actuality represent the external world and always lead the knower towards what is beyond them. Thus the verisimilitude of conceptions is always actual.

The general Correspondence between knowledge and the known is one of the necessary characteristics of knowledge. More clearly stated, the reality of knowledge is one which represents the external world, so a scientific assumption that is not representative of the outside is an impossible one. It is also impossible to assume that there is a kind of knowledge that discovers and represents the outside without having something discovered out of it.[10]

In this theory, the actual value of concepts and conceptions has been taken into consideration. In other words, we are realists with regard to our conceptions. Although conception is always accompanied with a mental form, this form will always direct us towards what is out of it. As a result, when dealing with conceptual concepts, we will be in relation to reality. One of the concomitants of this theory is that there must be no error in conceptions; for example, the senses cannot commit any error. Through accepting the validity of all conceptions, 'Allamah tries to justify the mechanism of error in conceptions. Mulla Sadra, too, is of the same view.[11]

Second view: The actual conception does not recount the external world; it rather represents the outside world. Conception, by itself, cannot represent the external world, while it is capable of recounting it. If another conception, relation or judgment is added to it; in other words, if that conception becomes a part of a proposition and is accompanied with assent, it will represent the world outside. In this way, the conception of subject along with that of the predicate can present its referent in the external world. Thus if conception is considered by itself, it will be potentially a representative of the external world, and what brings this potentiality into actuality is an annex consisting of the very judgment and assent.

Conception is a simple mental phenomenon which is capable of recounting what is beyond itself, such as the conception of Mount Damawand and the concept of mountain.[12]

Therefore, regarding the two types of acquired knowledge - conception and assent - we could say that it is only assent which is of actual epistemological value. Concepts, by themselves, cannot represent the reality. In fact, we have just discussed the details with respect to the different types of knowledge, and we have been realists only in terms of assents.

Third view: Conceptions, whatever form they have, are of no epistemological value. They even have no potential value, for conception is nothing more than the existence of a thing in our cognitive perceptions. Such a thing can never lead us to the external world. This is because these are only assents that are capable of unveiling and representing the outside. One can only be a realist with respect to assents; therefore, conceptions, even potentially, are not capable of unveiling the reality and recounting it.[13]

This theory is not acceptable because, firstly, a specific conception always develops under specific conditions. For instance, if we open our eyes to a liquid, we will see it as water. If we go out of the house in a cold winter day, we feel cold, and if we do the same in a hot summer day, we feel hot. When we see a particular thing, we always see it in the color it has, for example, green, and if we turn our back to it, we will see something else. These facts indicate that the development of conceptions in our mind is rooted in certain causes that are out of it, thus the conceptions recount these causes in the external world. We can also refer to the variety of conception. The variety of conceptions has no reason except for the variety of their bases and causes. Therefore, a specific conception originates from a specific source, corresponds to it, and recounts it. Second, the denial of the recounting feature of conceptions is the same as the denial of the principle of causality. This is because sense conceptions, for example, appear as effects for the soul, and the mind is affected when sensing something. If sensing is the same as being affected, according to the principle of causality, it requires something effective. The effective agent cannot leave an effect at its own level; therefore, it is out of its own level and plays a role in the development of a notional effect in the mind. Such sensory effects will naturally recount and report external effective agents. Third, if we do not view conceptions realistically, when dealing with self-evident perceptions, we can never consider them or their content as being true, while Muslim philosophers view them and their content, whether notional or affirmative (related to assent), as being true. This is one of the points that relates the problem of conceptions and assents to the discussion of immediate perceptions or self-evident issues. One who denies the ability to recount conceptions, and separates them from reality can never acknowledge the truth of self-evident conceptions in the context of immediate perceptions, and if he does, he has in fact adopted two contradictory positions. This judgment also includes the second view, since the ability to recount means that if we take conception into account by itself, without relating it to a proposition, it is not capable of representing the reality. In sum, any theory which disrupts the connection between conception (since it is a conception) and the external world - whether with the ability to recount or without it - cannot vote for the truth of self-evident conception, and if it does, it has spoken contradictorily.

Realism itself is of two direct and indirect types and means to acknowledge that whatever we perceive, for example through our senses, exist independently of our experiences and possess at least some of the features we believe they do. Direct realism means having a notional perception of an object without the perception of an intermediary. On the contrary, indirect realism means perceiving an object through an intermediary. According to this classification, we can say that the first view is in line with indirect realism, for, on the one hand, it indicates that conception represents the external world and, on the other hand, since conception is a kind of acquired knowledge, it is accompanied with an intermediary or form. However, a person like Shaykh al-Ishraq, who considers the sense as knowledge by presence, believes in direct realism, and if one denies the relation between conception and the external world and does not consider it as representing the reality, from an epistemological point of view, agrees with a kind of cognitive phenomenology, and is in fact satisfied with appearances in the context of conceptions. Such appearances could never come together with realities.

Judgment (hukm)

Since judgment is the criterion for assent, as well as a distinctive feature separating conception from assent, it is necessary to inquire into the reality and nature of judgment prior to dealing with assent. There are different views as to the problem of judgment. In what follows we will explain these views in detail.

A. Judgment is one of the acts of the soul.

When we make a judgment, an act has been emanated from our soul. Therefore, the relation between judgment and the soul is an emanating one rather than an immanent one. The soul is not the place of judgment; it is its origin. In this sense, judgment is the same as will, and both emanate from the soul. Accordingly, judgment is not of the type of accidents which indwell in the soul. The soul has in fact a causal relation to accidents. This idea has been attributed to Qutb al-Din Razi (refer to his treatise), Suhrawardi (al-Talwihat andMutarihat ), Ibn Kamunah (his glosses uponal-Talwihat ), and Fakhr al-Din Razi.[14] Reference has also been made to this idea inSharh al-mawaqif without attributing it to a specific person.[15]

This view has been criticized on the grounds that assent is one of the types of knowledge, and that philosophers consider knowledge as a passive accident or mental quality. Therefore, how is it possible for judgment, which is one of the constituents of assent, to be one of the acts of the soul? Two answers have been given to this question:

1. Assent, which is accompanied with judgment, belongs to the category of act; however, it is not a type of knowledge. It is, in fact, parallel to knowledge and a point of division for it. In other words, knowledge is only limited to conceptions. The minor proposition has been eliminated from this response; that is, assent has been placed out of the domain of knowledge so that judgment could sustain its actuality.[16]

2. This idea involves a metaphoric language, since judgment is not an act of the soul. A conception that necessitates the passing of a judgment is the act of the soul. Here we have applied the act of the soul to the necessary rather than to the necessitated, which is a kind of metaphor. This response has been provided by Qutb al-Din Razi.[17]

B. Judgment is a kind of perception rather than act.

In this approach, judgment is considered an epistemological issue. The followers of this idea believe that if we view perception as an act of the soul, it will not be an epistemological issue anymore; in other words, being an act of the soul and recounting the reality are not consistent with each other, and cannot come together in the same place. Therefore, they emphasize that judgment is not an act and, in this way, decree that it is related to perception. The author ofQistas , Qutb al-Din Razi, Taftazani, and Mohammed Dawani are among the followers of this idea.[18] This view has also been discussed inSharh al-mawaqif .[19]

There are certain arguments for this view:

1. If man refers to his heart, he finds out that whenever he makes a judgment, it means that he has gained some knowledge. Making a judgment is the same as learning something new, and refuting a judgment is the same as losing some piece of knowledge and increasing one’s ignorance. Therefore, a clear and peaceful conscience testifies to the perceptual nature of judgment.

2. Judgment is the result of thinking, which is a kind of perception. Since thinking belongs to the category of perception, its result will also be the same.

3. Judgment can be qualified by attributes which are in conformity with being a perception, for example, judgment is said to be acquired. As we know, we acquire both knowledge and perceptions.

The last view suffers from certain drawbacks, as follows:

a. One could refute this view and claim that as his inner sense or conscience indicates, when passing a judgment, an act emanates from him. Furthermore, conscience-related issues are not essentially acceptable as proof, since conscience is something personal, and personal issues are not universal, while a piece of proof has to be universal and generalizable, and we must be able to present it to others and use it as a tool when exchanging ideas.

b. If we accept that judgment is the outcome of thinking, we can say that, firstly, not every judgment is the result of thinking, since there are also self-evident judgments. Secondly, one might say that theoretical judgments, which are the result of thinking, prepare the mind for issuing acts, and this act is the very judgment. Thus if something is the result of thinking, it does not necessarily mean that it is perceptual and not an act of the soul.

C. Judgment is a revealing act.

To tell the truth, both of the above-mentioned views include some facts. On the one hand, judgment could be one of the acts of the soul, since, first, the words used in the phrasing of a judgment, including 'I state’, 'I admit’, I confirm, all have a content, denote the completing of an action, and report the emanation of an act from the soul. Therefore, it is the language of judgment and its assent that necessitate considering the reality of judgment as a psychic action. Second, the analysis of the nature of the proposition leads to the fact that judgment belongs to the category of acts. For example, if we see a red apple in the outside world, we have in fact encountered something and seen an object. In other words, what is seen and what makes one see something are both a single thing. When this single thing comes to the mind, it is divided and analyzed into two different things. The mind considers the concept of apple as a substantial one and views redness as an accidental essence. At the second level, the mind deals with two different concepts, the concept of apple and the concept of redness. At the same time, the mind pays attention to the point that in the outside and at the first level of the mind, there was only one thing, the red apple. In order to bring the second level of the mind into harmony with the external reality and acknowledge and present this act, man constructs a proposition. In this way, he places the concept of apple in the position of the subject, and the concept of redness in the position of the predicate, then establishes a relation between them and evaluates them in the light of each other, and finally makes a judgment as to the unity of these two concepts - subject and the predicate - in the outside, and admits its truth and applicability. Through passing a judgment, the mind intends to create a unitary relation between the subject and predicate in the outside and admit it. The proposition, which is related to the third level of the mind, returns to the first level, which is encountering a single thing, and is, in fact, a kind of combination after analysis. The philosophy beyond constructing a proposition basically is to admit the external unity of the subject and the predicate. This is the first building block of any proposition. The essence of a proposition is to bring two things, the subject and the predicate, together. The unity of these two concepts takes place in the context of reality, and if there is no external gotogetherness, there will be no proposition, and if there is any, it will be void of meaning and spirit. Assuming a proposition without the unity of its two sides in the outside is the same as assuming a proposition without a proposition. In other words, there would be a paradoxical and self-contradictory concept. Therefore, if we construct a proposition to establish a unity between the subject and predicate, and we show this relation through judgment, we have no choice but to admit that judgment is the act of the soul and the mind.

On the other hand, judgment should represent what is beyond itself. As discussed before, the content of judgment aims at presenting the external unity between the subject and the predicate, thus theoretical judgment, too, deals with the outside and recounts and reports external unity. In this way, one can prove the representational nature of judgment. In other words, the judgment’s being an act, and its perceptual and epistemological aspects are not mutually exclusive. We can assume something which could be an act of the soul on one hand, and represent what is beyond it, on the other.

Psychical issues are of two types: some of them like joy, will, and sorrow have no perceptual aspect. Such issues are not the forms of anything; for example, there is a clear distinction between joy and the conception of tree. The first is an absolutely psychical issue which bears no scientific and informational load, and is merely an internal state, while the second is a part of one’s knowledge, and of the type perceptual issues. Furthermore, such psychical states are revealed to the soul by means of knowledge by presence. Some of the other psychical issues have scientific and cognitive aspects but are passively acquired by the soul. Mental forms are of this type; that is, perceptual faculties, when encountering a real thing, receive its form and are influenced by external effects. For example, the conceptions of stone or sky are the forms of particular external things. All such conceptions are, firstly, the forms of objects and influence the soul; secondly, we have an acquired knowledge of them.

Judgment has both the aspects. One the one hand, it is a form representing the external world, in the sense that it reveals the external unity between the subject and the predicate, as well as the external existence of philosophical relation and copulative existence. From this aspect, judgment is a kind of acquired knowledge and mental form, representing and revealing the external world. One the other hand, judgment is the act of the soul, and, accordingly, it is like other psychical issues such as pleasure, will, and desire. From this aspect, judgment does not represent or discover anything. That is why it is called acknowledgement or judgment. From this point of view, judgment is merely an act of the soul, as the will is a psychical act. Therefore, it can be concluded that judgment has two aspects: on the one hand, it represents what is beyond itself; therefore, like all other sciences, it is of a scientific, cognitive, and perceptual nature. On the other hand, judgment, like the will, is an act of the soul and is created by it. When passing a judgment, the soul does the act of creating the objective unity between the subject and the predicate. Thus judgment is an act of the soul and, at the same time, opens a window towards the outside world. In sum, judgment is a revealing act. This idea was first proposed and developed by 'Allamah tabataba’i and Mutahhari.[20] However, it should be noted that Mulla Sadra’s writings had completely provided the grounds for adopting this idea.

Here, the previous objection is raised again, indicating that judgment is constituted in assent; assent is a kind of knowledge, and knowledge is among psychical accidents; therefore, judgment cannot be an act. Considering the last analysis, there are two answers to this objection:

1. We can make a major contradiction and deny the general principle that knowledge is an accident. Mulla Sadra emphasized that knowledge is an ontological issue, and this ontological issue is the act of the soul. The soul is the origin of the realization of all types of knowledge, and they are the effects of the soul.[21]

2. It was previously mentioned that judgment has two aspects and its revealing aspect was proved. From this aspect, judgment is a mental issue and a kind of acquired knowledge, and is passively obtained by the soul. As an accident or psychical quality, knowledge corresponds with this aspect of judgment.

D. Judgment is a conception which is followed by judgment.

Therefore, we can say that the term judgment is applied to conception, since it is followed by a judgment - assent. In other words, the name of a requiring agent is applied to what is required, and we have in fact employed a metaphor here. Apparently, the author ofDurrat al-taj is of the same view.[22]

It seems that the two terms, assent and judgment, have been confused with each other, since, as we will see later, a lot of views concerning assent suggest that conception follows judgment. Qutb al-Din Shirazi has based his definition of assent on judgment. However, it is emphasized that judgment is not the same as assent, and there are certain differences between them.

E. Judgment is the relation of the predicate to the subject.

This view is attributed to the commentator ofQistas. [23] If we state that a proposition consists of four components, subject, predicate, relation, and judgment, it indicates that judgment is the same as the third component. The relation established between the subject and predicate is called judgment.

F. Judgment is not the same as the relation between the subject and the predicate; rather, it is the perception of this relation.

From this point of view, judgment, in affirmative propositions, means the perception of the occurrence of relation, and, in negative propositions, it means the perception of non-occurrence of relation. This view has been attributed to the commentator ofMatali .[24]

A general review of earlier views can help us in making a more limited classification of all of them. The last view apparently indicates that judgment is the same as perception. This idea is related to the second one, in which the subject of perception is determined. On the other hand, the fifth view is very close to the first one, since if judgment is a relation between the subject and predicate, it is, in fact, an act of the soul; therefore, this theory views the nature of judgment as an act of the soul. By reducing the above-mentioned ideas to a more general and, at the same time, more limited classification, it could be said that there are three principle views concerning the nature of judgment: 1) judgment is a perceptual issue; 2) judgment is a psychical act; 3) judgment is a revealing act. Out of these three ideas, the last one is the correct one, and the discussions presented so far confirm the truth of this claim.

In order to clarify the nature of judgment, two points are worth a mention: First, judgment is not a relation. Whenever two concepts are presented to the mind, it considers one as the subject and the other as the predicate in a proposition, and after their conception, the mind relates and compares the subject and the predicate to each other. This act, which is the same judgmental relation, is one of the mental functions that is performed when dealing with a proposition. The comparison may be made between two distinctive forms or concepts, such as body and white, or between something and itself, such as man and himself; that is, the mind is capable of considering a single concept in two different ways and, in this way, establish a proposition in which a concept is predicated on itself. In such cases, of course, the predication will be essential. It is necessary to emphasize that judgment is other than a relation or comparison between two sides of a proposition; it is rather the acknowledgement of the realization of this relation. When the mind makes a comparison between two concepts, it either admits their unity or does not; in this way, we have either an affirmative or negative proposition. In either case acknowledgement and passing a judgment are mental acts that appear after making a comparison between the subject and predicate. This is because judgment is affirmed or negated, while relations in propositions are not such. It should also be added that judgment requires a subject, and that relation is the subject of judgment. Therefore, it is not possible to have a judgment without a relation; however, we could assume a case in which there is a relation between two concepts, without having a judgment involved. Therefore, if there is a judgment in a proposition, there will necessarily be a relation. Of course, it can be said that relation is not a part of the proposition and, thus, as 'Allamah tabataba’i maintains,[25] eliminate it from the nature of proposition. Nevertheless, the existence of judgment is necessary, since judgment has no subject except for relation.

The second point is that judgment is not the same as association of meanings. Sometimes, something reminds man of something else simply due to their similarity, adjacency, or contrast. The reason for this is nothing except for habit and mental familiarity. For example, since man has always witnessed day and night succeeding each other, he always expects the day to be followed by the night and vice versa. Or since he has always heard the name of Hatam ta’i in association with generosity, whenever he hears this name, he is reminded of generosity. Association of meanings is one of the mental functions attracting the attention of psychologists. Now it is necessary to pay attention to the point that judgment is not the same as association of meanings. In judgment we do not move from the subject to the predicate or vice versa out of a mental habit. The reality of judgment is other than the association of meanings, since there are many propositions which are presented to man for the first time, like scientific hypotheses concerning which man has no background knowledge, familiarity, and mental habit. In such cases the scientist evaluates the issue through empirical and inductive methods, and then passes a scientific judgment. Here there is no trace of association of meanings, but there is a judgment. On the contrary, sometimes there might be an association of meanings involved, for example, we might be reminded of generosity by hearing the name of Hatam ta’i; at the same time, we may make a judgment, or even for some reason, judge that Hatam was not a generous man.

In sum, judgment is not the same as relation in propositions and is issued after establishing a relation. In the same way, it is not the same as the association of meanings. Judgment is a mental act which the mind performs in order to refer to what is beyond them and unveil the reality.

Assent (tasdiq)

From what was said above, it can be concluded that assent is always accompanied with judgment and relies on it. Without judgment, there could be no assent. In sum, the basis of assent and what distinguishes it from conception is judgment. After getting familiar with different ideas and theories of judgment, it would be useful to study the relation between assent and judgment. In other words, all the discussions so far indicated that assent is in a way related to judgment; however, the quality of this relation has not been dealt with yet. This relation can be explained in different ways, and there are a number of views concerning this issue, as follows:

First View:

Assent is the same as judgment. According to this view, assent and judgment are no different from each other. In other words, there is a relation of equality between assent and judgment. Of course, one can adopt any view concerning the nature of judgment, and this view will naturally explain the nature of assent as well. This view is quite popular among philosophers.[26] It seems that Sabziwari,[27] Muhaqqiq Têsi,[28] and Qutb al-Din Razi[29] confirm this view, Mulla Sadra considers it as being weak.[30]

Second View:

Assent is a composite. This view is attributed to Fakhr al-Din Razi.[31] However, there are some debates over whether assent is a combination of three components, the conception of subject, the conception of predicate, and the judgmental relation, or a combination of four components, the above-mentioned three components along with judgment. Qutb al-Din Razi[32] believes that in Fakhr al-Din Razi’s view assent consists of three components, whereas Iji[33] and Sabziwari[34] side with the second view. Mulla Sadra, however, does not adopt a specific position in this regard, and has his doubts about each of them.[35]

A review of Fakhr al-Din Razi’s words suggest that he believes that assent consists of four components[36] and considers judgment as one of the pillars of assent rather than its true nature. In sum, according to Fakhr al-Din Razi, assent is a composite of four elements, namely, subject, predicate, relation, and judgment.

In this sense, assent is the same as a proposition. Fakhr al-Din Razi presents a definition for assent that only corresponds with the definition of a proposition. As a result, for him and his followers, assent is the same as proposition; of course, this is true only if we consider a proposition as a composite of four parts. However, there are other views and positions which are worth our attention.