4.Eddington’s
Two Tables and the Elimination of Everyday Objects
When it comes to tables, we have been here before, of course, with the famous case ofEddington
and his ‘two tables’. In the introduction to his popular exposition, based on his Gifford lectures (1928), he compares the ‘commonplace’ table which has extension, iscoloured
and ‘above all’ is substantial, with the ‘scientific’ table, which is mostly empty and is not substantial at all (ibid., pp. xi-xiii). It is the latter that is ‘really there’, whereas the former is an illusion (ibid., p. 323). Presented thus, this seems a standard example of the presentation of scientificeliminativism
. This is certainly howStebbing
views it in her dismissal ofEddington’s
claims as ‘preposterous nonsense’ (1937, p. 54). Her core objection is that the object of scientific descriptions is not the ‘table’, as this term is used in common discourse, and thus there cannot be two tables, with one granted ontological priority over the other. Furthermore, the ‘scientific’ cannot duplicate, and consequently replace, the everyday, since the properties of the latter, such ascolour
, cannot be duplicated via entities that do not possess such properties.
Now,Stebbing
is certainly right in pointing out thatEddington’s
language and lack of training in philosophy does not help his case. More importantly, his articulation of the relationship between ‘everyday’ objects and the entities we should take as fundamental is less than clear in the passages she considers. Nevertheless, a more charitable reading would have filtered out the rhetoric deployed in the service of a set of public lectures and perhaps pulled together arguments and claims from acrossEddington’s
works, both scientific and popular, in order to produce a (more) rational reconstruction of his position. Two aspects of these works might then have become clear. The first is that like many who have sought a radical ontologicalreconceptualisation
,Eddington
struggles to find a language that is not corrupted by the very ontology he is trying to replace. The cost of constructing such a language is evident in the difficulty one encounters in trying to understand his final work which attempted to construct a form of quantum gravity (1946). This ontology that he is trying to get away from is one of things and, in particular, substances. This brings us to the second aspect, which isEddington’s
structuralism, something thatStebbing
fails to grasp (see French 2003)
. The crucial feature of ‘everyday’ objects thatEddington
wants to eliminate from our ontology is their substantiality and, as with otherstructuralists
of the time, such as Cassirer, his structuralism can becharacterised
in those terms. How one expressed that elimination was a central problem forEddington
but it can be understood as an appropriatelycontextualised
version of the issue we are facing here, namely how tocharacterise
and represent the relationship between ‘everyday’ objects and the underlying structures that physics presents to us.
Stebbing’s
attack has been taken up again more recently byThomasson
(2007) who defends an ontology of ordinary objects againsteliminativist
arguments. She explicitly addresses the impact of science on such an ontology, identifying two forms of this impact (ibid.,
Ch. 7): according to one, associated withEddington
, science and the ‘everyday’ are in conflict; according to the other, associated withSellars
, they are merely rivals. With regard to the first, there can be only conflict if the two sides are talking about the same thing.
However, here again,sortal
considerations enter the picture asThomasson
argues that reference to things is fixed via some categorical framework. Hence, she maintains that,
‘… scientific theories … do not usesortals
such as ‘table’, and if science and common sense are usingsortals
of different categories, the ‘things’ picked out by the two descriptions cannot be identical.’ (Thomasson
2007, p. 142)
One might try to present the conflict in terms of some neutral sense of ‘thing’ but ‘thing’ in that sense would not then be asortal
term and could not be used to establish reference. Or one could appeal to a common notion of ‘physical object’ or ‘occupant of aspatio
-temporal region’, but, she argues, the first finds no place within physicsitself
, and the second is hardly common in everyday descriptions. Hence there is no conflict between science and ordinary discourse: both have their distinctontologies
.
With regard to theSellarsian
view of a rivalry between the ‘scientific image’ and the ‘manifest image’, in which the former has primacy over the latter,Thomasson
again argues that any account of what there is presupposes a certainsortal
framework. Such accounts can only offer a complete description in terms of that framework in the sense of covering all the things in those categories. However, the scientific and manifest images presuppose differentsortal
frameworks and hence cannot be complete in any way that renders them rivals (ibid., p. 148). Consequently, acceptance of the scientific image does not require rejection of the ontology of the manifest.
Eddington’s
position is also undermined, according toThomasson
, not least because on astructuralist
interpretation, there is a ‘… lack of conflict between the merely structural properties physics imputes to the world and the qualitative content involved in ordinary world descriptions.’(ibid., p. 139).
Now, the distinction between structure and content is one that has arisen repeatedly in discussions over structural realism but it evaporates as far as theontic
form is concerned, since all relevant content is taken to be cashed out in structural terms. Insofar as the ‘qualitative content’ thatThomasson
refers to goes beyond this, it becomes part of the more general issue having to do with the relationship between the scientific and the ‘everyday’.
Here a number of concerns arise, not the least being thatThomasson’s
account creates a vastly inflationary ontology. Let me be clear about this: it is not thatThomasson
is claiming that ordinary objects are somehow derivative; rather, they count as metaphysically robust elements of our ontology, just as elementary particles are. As a result her metaphysics is entirely detached from the relevant physics, since the latter incorporates an assortment of physical relations that hold between, for example, protons, neutrons andelectons
, atoms and molecules, molecules and polymers and so on. One option for the kind of naturalistic approach indicated previously is to explore the possibility of meshing the metaphysics with the physics by constructing metaphysical relations that effectively track the physical ones; another, as we shall see, is to radically reconfigure the relevant ontology so as to remove the necessity for positing certain such relations. Either way, we keep the metaphysics and physics in touch with each other, as it were, rather than cleaving them entirely apart asThomasson
does.
A further major worry has to do with the central role played bysortal
frameworks in her view
. First of all, it is also worth noting the difficulty involved in constructing such a framework in the quantum context, particularly if one adopts the view of quantum particles as non-individuals (French and Krause 2006b). Of course, this may be taken as further fuel forThomasson’s
position, since if the relevant frameworks are so different, not just in terms of the kinds of things they cover, but in terms of their underlying metaphysics and even logic, then how can then be said to rival or compete with one another? However efforts are being made to relate the two kinds of framework and attempts to construct a form of ‘quantummereology
’ can be seen as contributing to the establishment of an appropriate relationship. If these efforts are successful then one might regard this as bringing the logic and metaphysics into line with the physics, insofar as the explanations of the latter can be taken to relate the frameworks concerned.
The issue then is whether the establishment of such a relationship effectively guts the ontology of the ‘manifest’ framework by reducing it to the scientific. Consider a general metaphysicalcharacterisation
of such relationships in terms of ‘grounding’, say:a
is
said to be grounded inb
in the sense thata
holds in virtue ofb
, without it being the case that onlyb
exists. Thus the ‘fact’ of there being a table in front of me (orEddington
) is grounded in facts about the relevant aggregate of quantum particles in the sense that the former fact holds in virtue of the latter (seeNorth
forthcoming, p. 26). Now, explanatory relations such as this crop up elsewhere, of course and offer a broader framework than, say, causal accounts, whilst nottrivialising
the relationships as deductive accounts do. However, as we saw in our brief discussion of dependence above, one worry here is that if we take this relation seriously, metaphysically speaking, then the kind of dependence that ‘in virtue of’ signifies effectively evacuates all there is toa
infavour
of the relevant features ofb
. If all there is toa
is
explained in terms of features ofb
, then what is left that has any independent existence? Of course, one might point to standard examples, such as the explanation of the shadow cast by the flagpole in terms of its height, the angle of the sun and some elementary geometry and insist that this does not imply that the shadow does not exist. However – leaving aside issues as to the nature of shadows – this just pushes the issue back a step or two: once I have given the best and most complete explanation available, articulated in terms of quantum field theory perhaps, then what is there to a shadow, as an object in its own right, that is not cashed out in terms of features that are more fundamental?
Talk of ‘facts’ here may actually obscure the issue: granted that the fact expressed in the claim ‘there is a table in front of me’ is a ‘real’, albeit non-fundamental fact (North op. cit.), this does not imply that the table itself should be taken as an element of our ontology. Consider the property thatStebbing
focuses on in her critique ofEddington
, namely solidity. As already noted, this holds in virtue of the relevant physics as expressed in the Exclusion Principle and, more fundamentally, theantisymmetrisation
of the relevant aggregate wave function. In this case one might then insist that the latter feature of quantum mechanics entirely explicates the solidity of everyday objects and in doing so eliminates the predicate from the scope of our fundamental ontology. Of course, as we shall see, one may still utter truths about tables, how solid they are and so on and these truths may be regarded as further facts beyond those that are fundamental, but one can still have all this and deny that the entities exist. I shall return to this point shortly.
There is also an obvious concern here thatThomasson
appears to have introduced a form ofsortal
relativism into this context. Note that the role ofsortals
in her account is different from the role they play in Hawley’s approach: in the latter case, it is the composition relations that are tied to differentsortal
frameworks; inThomasson’s
case, it is the existence of objects. The latter has obvious problematic implications for realism. This is something that Schaffer takes up in his critical review (2009): the invocation of appropriatesortal
concepts is crucial for various aspects ofThomasson’s
account but in particular, existence claims appear to besortal
relative (ibid., p. 149). This would not only have radical implications for the semantics of existential quantification (ibid.), but would also take her account outside of the broadly realist stance that is being adopted here. However, as Schaffer notes (ibid.),Thomasson
attempts to evade this conclusion and retain the standard account of simple quantification while maintaining her radical conclusions about everyday ontology, by arguing that what her account of reference determination viasortal
frameworks does is specify thedomain
of quantification. Thus, existence claims are only evaluable once an appropriate domain is specified, where that involves specifying or presupposing the relevant sorts of entities involved (Thomasson
, op. cit. pp. 464-465).
In response, Schaffer points out (op. cit., p. 150) that althoughsortals
can act as perfectly good domainspecifiers
, so can properties, for example, and so we don’t need to dally withsortal
relativism. But thenThomasson’s
defence
ofan ontology
of ordinary objects would fall apart. Furthermore, Schaffer argues that we can straightforwardly specify the total domain of ‘everything’ and do so in a way that does not involve a non-category-specific sense of ‘thing’ (ibid., pp. 150-151). Again, with the prop ofsortal
specificity taken away,Thomasson’s
account collapses. And for our purposes here, the latter response allows us to talk of the universal domain, as it were, while the former allows us to talk of putative things belonging to different domains, and the relationships between them, without presupposing asortal
framework that, in effect, existentially neuters these relationships. Obviously ‘domain’ here is better understood as ‘level’, so we can now talk of the relationship between the level of ordinary objects, such as tables, and that of elementary particles, without having to accept that the specification of such levels necessarily involvessortals
in terms of which distinctontologies
must be acknowledged, asThomasson
demands. In particular, we can articulate a reductive relationship in terms of which such ordinary objects are eliminated.
Eliminativism
about ordinary objects may seem a radical position to adopt
but it is one that meshes with our understanding of contemporary physics, according to which there is only a limited number of certain fundamental kinds of elementary particles and four fundamental forces – everything else is effectively composed out of these. I aim to take this picture seriously, in the sense of indicating, in at least a preliminary way, how an appropriate metaphysics might be constructed on this basis
.
Now one reason this seems such a radical line to take is that we have considerable everyday experience of tables: we use them in various ways, set chairs around them,bump
into them and so on. Thus we face a dilemma: according toeliminativism
, tables don’t exist and yet the statement ‘Tables exist’ appears to be true! Indeed, the fact expressed by such a statement might well be taken to be ‘Moorean
’ in the sense that we have better knowledge of it than the premises of any argument that seeks to deny it. In that sense, it trumps any attempt ateliminativism
. However, this is a dangerous line to take as it would not simply underminescepticism
as in Moore’s ‘here is a hand’ case, but would preclude the possibility of the kind of reductive analysis that physics appears to push us toward.
Let me now briefly sketch different metaphysicalmanoeuvres
we candeply
to help resolve the above dilemma: