The Primacy and Gradation of Being
The word 'asalah
', meaning to be principal and primary, refers to that which is real and gives actual reality to existents in the extra-mental world. The main questionSadra
asks is which of the two, being orquiddity
,
has ‘reality’ in the external world. The philosophical significance of this question cannot be overemphasized for traditional philosophy that considered truthand
reality to be intertwined. The Arabic wordhaqiqah
can be translated as both true and real, and this is essential for finding that which is the basis of things in truth and reality. Such a thing accounts for ontological affirmation and epistemic credibility – the two qualities really existing beings have. Being (al-wujud
) as the principal reality thus establishes things in concrete existence and saturates them with meaning.
Simple as it may seem, though, this idea has a long history in Islamic thought.
Ibn
Sin
a
was content with recapitulating the distinction between being andquiddity
since his primary concern was to lay out a tripartite division of existents as impossible (
mumtani
’
), contingent (
mumkin
) and necessary (
wajib
), and draw a categorical distinction between the last two, i.e., the created and the Creator.
Even thoughIbn
Sina
did not deal with the primacy or non-primacy of being in any clear manner and his discussions can be read to support and oppose either position, the key issue for his medieval interpreters, especially in the Latin West, was his discussion and alleged espousal of theaccidentality
of being. The problem had emanated fromIbn
Sina’s
somewhat recondite analysis of how being is related to essence (
mahiyyah
). St. Thomas Aquinas and other Scholastic philosophers readIbn
Sina
as arguing that being is an accident conferred upon things antecedently. In simple terms, things exist and theirquiddities
require being only as an accident or attribute without which they can survive the abyss of non-existence. Interestingly enough, this (mis
)interpretation goes back toIbn
Rushd
.
Sadra
and his followers took a different approach and interpretedIbn
Sina
as saying that being is a ‘special accident’ in the case of contingent beings (mumkin
al-wujud
): the existence of contingent beings is a ‘borrowed existence’ and depends on the Necessary Being (wajib
al-wujud
) for their subsistence. This implies that contingent or possible beings ‘receive’ their existence from another source antecedently or, to use the language of theology, from high on. Now, we may conceive being as an accident (‘arad
) ‘happening’ to things because their concrete existence is not required by mental abstraction or, as Aristotle would say, by definition. More importantly, being is an ‘attribute’ granted to created things by God who, as the Necessary Being, sustains them in existence. Considered from the point of view of extra-mental existence (al-wujud
al-‘ayni
), however, being is not added to thingsa posteriori
, otherwise we would have to assume that things take on being as an accident without which they can ‘exist’ – a logically absurd and impossible conclusion.
Suhrawardi
, with whomSadra
utterly differs on this particular question, foundeda metaphysics
of essences when he definedquiddity
(al-mahiyyah
) as the sole agent that constitutes reality.Suhrawardi
proposed two objections against the primacy of being. First, if we take existence, he said, as a real attribute of essence, then essence, in order to have this attribute, has to exist prior to existence in which case existence would be a quality of something that already exists.
Secondly, if existence is considered to be the real constituent of reality, then existence will have to exist before being a constituent of external reality and this second existence will have to exist, and so onad infinitum
.
Suhrawardi’s
conclusion was a turning point in the history of Islamic thought. His claim that being is only a generic term, a secondary intelligible (ma‘qul
thani
), applicable to a multitude of object but to which nothing concrete corresponds in the extra-mental world, heralded the beginning of a long controversy especially in the Persian speaking world.Sadra
rejected this deduction by saying that we cannot logically say 'existence exists' just as we do not say 'whiteness is white'. Existence exists by itself. In other words, the actualization of being in the external world occurs by itself and not through something else.
When I say that “the tree exists”, I do not take the tree and its existence to be two separate and separable realities. The tree as a particular being and itsquiddity
are given in one and the same thing all at once. Therefore being is not something that has existence just as whiteness is not something that has whiteness.
Being is that very reality by virtue of which things exist just as whiteness is that by virtue of which things are white.
According toSadra
,Suhrawardi's
false conclusion results from confusing the concept and reality of existence. When conceived by the mind, being is a universal concept without a corresponding reality in the extra-mental world. And it is at this level of abstraction that we can take existence as an attribute of something. That is why we can think of essences without their actual existence in the physical world.
Said differently, existence as the most general notion in the mind cannot be a basis for the reality of individual existents.
The reality of being defies all such conceptualization. Although at the level of conceptual analysis one is allowed to say that existence is 'something that has existence' (shay’lahu
al-wujud
) in reality, its basic structure is that it is existence by itself or existentpar excellence
(al-wujud
huwa
al-mawjudiyyah
).
Sadra
's
conclusion is thus diametrically opposed to that ofSuhrawardi
: being is not an extraneous quality imposed upon existents but the very reality thanks to which they exist.
In rejectingSuhrawardi’s
essentialist ontology,Sadra
reiterates an old issue in Islamic philosophy, i.e., whether being is a predicate or not, the word ‘predicate’ being used here in its logical sense as denoting some property or attribute of actually existing things. As in Western philosophy since Kant
, the Muslim philosophers have usually answered this question in the negative but introduced an important distinction between the logical and ontological senses of existential propositions. From a logical point of view, we can analyze the sentence “this table is oak” into a subject and predicate. The subject of the sentence, “this table”, is a noun and the predicate “oak” also a noun and an attribute qualifying the table.
Now, we can turn this sentence, composed of a subject and a predicate, into an existential proposition by saying that “the table is”, “the table exists”, or “the table is an existent”. When we look at these sentences from a logical point of view, existence, stated by the copula, turns out to be a predicate and attribute qualifying the table. From the ontological point of view, however, this conclusion is absurd because it assumes the existence of the table prior to its having existence as an attribute. Given that the table in question is a real existent, the moment we say ‘table’, we have already affirmed its extra-mental reality. In light of this, one may say that Descartes’cogito ergo sum
argument is flawed because from a strictly ontological point of view, the moment I say ‘I’ in the sentence “I think, therefore I am”, I have already affirmed my existence.
al-Farabi
was the first to have noted this philosophical difficulty and proposed two ways of looking at such existential propositions. In the proposition “man exists”, existence, al-Farabi
reasoned, is both a predicate and not a predicate. From the point of view of the ‘logician’ (al-nazir
al-mantiqi
), the sentence has a predicate because it is composed of two terms, subject and predicate, and is liable of being true or false. From the standpoint of the ‘natural scientist’ (al-nazir
al-tabi’i
), which here means the ontological point of view, however, it does not because the “existence of something is nothing but itself”.
The most important conclusion thatSadra
derives from this analysis is that being is not an attribute conferred upon things antecedently. It is their very reality which makes them what they are, and forSadra
, this proves the primacy of being.
Having established being as the primary reality,Sadra
turns to the question of how being applies to individual entities which he calls ‘shares of being’ (khisas
al-wujud
). Insofar as we talk about things as actually existing, being is predicated of all things that exist. In this most generic sense, being applies to things univocally, signifying their common state of existence.Sadra
, however, takes a further step and argues that the predication of being takes place with varying degrees of ‘intensity’ (tashaddud
), which he explains by using the word ‘gradation’ (tashkik
).
To give an example, light is predicated of the candle, the moon and the sun univocally in that they all participate in the quality of light, luminosity and brightness. Each of these objects, however, displays different degrees of intensity in sharing the quality of light. Light is the most intense and brightest in the sun and weakest in the reflection of the moonlight on the pool. By the same token, being is predicated of the Creator, the source of all beings, and the created in that they both exist. Their share of existence, however, is not the same because God is ontologically prior and superior to contingent beings. Having the most intense state of existence, God has more ‘being’ than other things, which is another way of emphasizing the ontological discontinuity between the Creator and the created.
The same analogy holds true for cause and effect since cause, by definition, precedes effect in the chain of causation: it causes the effect to be what it is, and this imparts on it a higher ontological status.Sadr
a
calls this “predication byequivocality
” (
haml
bi’l-tashkik
)
.
Sadr
a
applies gradation to the entire spectrum of being: things partake of being with different degrees of intensity and diminution, strength and weakness, priority and posterity, perfection and imperfection.
What is of particular importance for our discussion is that the same principle is applied to the order of thought as well, and
Sadr
a
explains degrees of knowledge in the same way as he explains degrees ofbeing.
As we shall see shortly, this is a crucial step towards formulatinga realist
ontology of intelligible substances, to which we now turn.