Change and Identity in Physical Bodies
After securing the material existence of physical bodies when they undergo substantial change,Sadra
proceeds to the most important and intricate part of his theory of substantial motion, which is the preservation of the identity of changing bodies. Reference was already made to the fact that differentia (al-fasl
), by definition, ensures the preservation of some quality or quantity-in-general despite the fact that the definite quality in the changing body is destroyed at every successive phase of its motion.Sadra
states that whatever has the final differentia as its principle of perfection has some sort of preservation-in-general. The redefinition of differentia as a thing’s principle of perfection becomes a forceful argument forSadra
because he seeks to replace the framework of traditional genus-differentia account with his gradational ontology. The differentia is now transformed from being a mere principle of difference (al-ikhtilaf
) amonggenuses
into a principle of existential individuation of particular entities. An important outcome of this reformulation is that differentia, viz. the principle of diversity and unity, is equated with being (al
-wujud
).Sadra
illustrates this point as follows:
Being capable of growth (al-nami
) is the plant’s differentia whereby its being is perfected, since its perfection is not due to its being a body alone. Rather, it (i.e., ‘being capable of growth’) is its principle of potency and carrier of its potentiality. Hence, there is no doubt that the change of bodily entities does not necessitate change in the substantial being of the plant itself since body is regarded here only in a general manner (‘alawajh
al-‘umum
wa’l-itlaq
), (i.e., as body-in-general), not in a specified and determined manner (‘alawajh
al-khususiyyah
wa’l-taqyid
) (i.e., not as body-in-particular). The same holds true for the animal which is constituted by being capable of growth and perception, and for every existent whose existence is constituted by matter and form such as man in relation to his soul and body. Hence when ‘being capable of growth’ changes in quantity, its ‘thing-ness
’ (jismiyyatahu
) as an individual entity also changes but its substantial structure as an individual entity remains the same. Thus it (i.e., the plant), insofar as it is a natural body-in-general, is destroyed as an individual entity, but, insofar as it is a natural body capable of growth, is not destroyed, neither itself nor even its part. Because every being part of which is nothing but body-in-general in an individual (entity) is established (in the external world) in a manner of continuous existence (al-ittisal
al-wujudi
). On the basis of this principle, the endurance of an animal together with its substance of perception can be explained. In the same manner, man in his old age loses most of his power of vegetation whereas his identity remains the same.
The foregoing description of qualitative and quantitative change holds true for all natural bodies that have a constantly changing being with an enduring identity. In every change and motion, there remains an original principle that is perfected by the final differentia. For example, the final differentia in composite beings comprises every successive phase of increasing perfection, which intensifying or moving bodies undergo. Therefore, the succession of various degrees of being, which leads physical bodies to a higher state of being, is not something added to the final differentia of corporeal bodies from outside. As we have stated before, a simple being (basit
al-haqiqah
) contains in itself all lower levels of being, and this principle is employed here bySadra
with full force to explain the peculiar relationship among species,genuses
, and differentia. Within this framework, every species comprises in its state of being whatever is possessed and shared by lower species. Equally important is the fact that species is perfected into a genus by differentia. The main point, however, is thatSadra
takes differentia not simply as a mental notion abstracted from physical entities as the principle of differentiation but equates it with being (wujud
), which functions, as we have seen, as the principle of unity as well as diversity inSadra’s
ontology.
The existential relationship between a physical body and its essential properties, or whatSadra
calls ‘concomitants’ (lawazim
), can also be explained by having recourse to the description of things in our ordinary language. When we want to define or describe something, we naturally refer to its essence as well as its essential properties that are included in its definition.Sadra
calls such properties ‘a mode of being’ (nahw
al-wujud
). In every mode of being, a particular piece of concrete reality appropriates and displays certain qualities that yield its ‘derived differentia’ (al-fasl
al-ishtiqaqi
). These distinctive qualities are generally called the ‘individual properties of a thing’ (al-mushakhkhasat
). They constitute whatSadra
calls the ‘signs of particularization’ (‘alamat
li’l-tashakhkhus
). Here is howSadra
summarizes his view:
The (word) sign here refers to the name of a thing by which its concept is expressed. In the same manner, the derived real differentia (al-fas l
al-
haq
iq
i
al-ishtiqa qi
) is described as logical differentia (al-fas l
al-mant iqi
) in the case of ‘being capable of growth’ (al-na mi
) for plants, sense perception for animals, and intellection for human beings. The first of these (descriptions) is a name for the vegetative soul, second for animal soul, and third for rational soul. These are all derived differentia. The same holds true for all other differentia with regard to composite substances (al-murakkaba t
al-jawhariyyah
). Each of these (bodies) is a simple substance designated by a universal logical differentia (fa
sl
mant iqi
kulli
) as a matter of naming things (tasmiyat
al-shay’
). These substances are, in fact, simple and specific (i.e., particularized) beings with noquiddity
.
In the same manner, the concomitants of individual entities are assigned to their individual possessors through naming. Thus, particularization is a mode of being. A particular entity becomes particularized by itself, andthese concomitant (properties) issue
forth from it just like the emanation of a ray of light from its source and of heat from fire.
The logical differentia as a universal refers to entities in the order of mental concepts whereas the real or existential differentia refers to their individuation and particularization (al-tashakhkhus
) in the order of being. At the conceptual level, we distinguish between a thing and its existential properties and thus obtain the essence-existence bifurcation. We apply such a conceptual process only ‘to name a thing’. In reality, however, there are only individuated concrete existents, simple and unique, without requiring any ‘quiddity
’. Particularization of a thing comes about by its assuming a mode of being with certain essential properties (al-mushahkhkasa t
). In other words, the relation between a body and its existential properties is reversed: a physical body does not become particularized due to appropriating such essential and/or accidental properties. On the contrary, these properties come into being as a result of thing’s particularization in the existential order just like the expansion of a beam of light from its original source of light.
Several conclusions can be drawn fromSadra’s
arguments. First of all, substance (jawhar
) changes in accordance with the change of its essential properties. With this, the dividing line between substance and accident becomes rather provisional. A material substance is thus essentially
a
substance that is by itself continuous, quantified, positional, temporal, and inhering in a definite place. The change of quantities, colors and positions of the substance necessitates the renewal of the definite quantity of the individuated material substance.
Thus, we arrive at a twofold picture of the natural world in which ‘material substances’ or ‘bodily natures’ are aptly regarded as the proper locus of two interrelated dimensions of physical entities: transience and perpetuity.
There is no doubt that every material substance has a continuously changing nature on the one hand, and an enduring and unchanging structure, on the other. The relationship between the two aspects is similar to the relationship between body and soul. While the body is in constant change and flow, the human soul endures because it preserves its identity by the passing of essential forms in an uninterrupted continuous process (wurud
al-amthal
‘ala’l-ittisal
).