Unity
All conscious experiences at any given point in an agent's life come as part of one unified conscious field.If I am sitting at my desk looking out the window, I do not just see the sky above and the brook below shrouded by the trees, and at the same time feel the pressure of my body against the chair, the shirt against my back, and the aftertaste of coffee in my mouth, rather I experience all of these as part of a single unified conscious field.
This unity of any state of qualitative subjectivity has important consequences for a scientific study of consciousness.I
say more about them later on. Atpresent
I just want to call attention to the fact that the unity is already implicit in subjectivity andqualitativeness
for the following reason: If you try to imagine that my conscious state is broken into 17 parts, what you imagine is not a single conscious subject with 17 different conscious states but rather 17 different centers of consciousness. A conscious state, in short, is by definition unified, and the unity will follow from the subjectivity and thequalitativeness
, because thereis
no way you could have subjectivity andqualitativeness
except with that particular form of unity.
There are two areas of current research where the aspect of unity is especially important. These are first, the study of the split-brain patients byGazzaniga
, (1998) and others (Gazzaniga
,Bogen
, and Sperry 1962, 1963), and second, the study of the binding problem by a number of contemporary researchers. The interest of the split-brain patients is that both the anatomical and the behavioral evidence suggest that in these patients there are two centers of consciousness that aftercommissurotomy
are communicating with each other only imperfectly. They seem to have, so to speak, two conscious minds inside one skull.
The interest of the binding problem is that it looks like this problem might give us in microcosm a way of studying the nature of consciousness, because just as the visual system binds all of the different stimulus inputs into a single unified visual percept, so the entire brain somehow unites all of the variety of our different stimulus inputs into a single unified conscious experience.
Several researchers have explored the role of synchronized neuron firings in the range of40hz
to account for the capacity of different perceptual systems to bind the diverse stimuli of anatomically distinct neurons into a single perceptual experience. (Llinas
1990,Llinas
and Pare 1991,Llinas
andRibary
1993,Llinas
and Ribary,1992
, Singer 1993, 1995, Singer and Gray, 1995,) For example in the case of vision, anatomically separate neurons specialized for such things as line, angle and color all contribute to a single, unified, conscious visual experience of an object. Crick (1994) extended the proposal for the binding problem to a general hypothesis about the NCC. He put forward a tentative hypothesis that the NCC consists of synchronized neuron firings in the general range of 40 Hz in various networks in thethalamocortical
system, specifically in connections between the thalamus and layers four and six of the cortex.
This kind of instantaneous unity has to be distinguished from the organized unification of conscious sequences that we get from short term or iconic memory. Fornonpathological
forms ofconsciousness
at least some memory is essential in order that the conscious sequence across time can come in an organized fashion. For example, whenI
speak a sentence I have to be able to remember the beginning of the sentence at the time I get to the end if I am to produce coherent speech. Whereas instantaneous unity is essential to, and is part of, the definition of consciousness, organized unity across time is essential to the healthy functioning of the conscious organism, but it is not necessary for the very existence of conscious subjectivity.
This combined feature of qualitative, unified subjectivity is the essence of consciousness and it, more than anything else, is what makes consciousness different from other phenomena studied by the natural sciences. The problem is to explain how brain processes, which are objective third person biological, chemical and electrical processes, produce subjective states of feeling and thinking. How does the brain get us over the hump, so to speak, from events in the synaptic cleft and the ion channels to conscious thoughts and feelings? If you take seriously this combined feature as the target of explanation,I
believe you get a different sort of research project from what is currently the most influential. Most neurobiologists take whatI
will call the building block approach: Find the NCC for specific elements in the conscious field such as the experience of color, and then construct the whole field out of such building blocks. Another approach, whichI
will call the unified field approach, would take the research problem to be one of explaining how the brain produces a unified field of subjectivity to start with. On the unified field approach, there are no buildingblocks,
rather there are just modifications of the already existing field of qualitative subjectivity.I
say more about this later.
Some philosophers and neuroscientists think we can never have an explanation of subjectivity: We can never explain why warm things feel warm and red things look red. To these skeptics there is a simple answer: We know it happens. We know that brain processes cause all of our inner qualitative, subjective thoughts and feelings. Because we knowthat
it happens we ought to try to figure out how it happens. Perhaps in theend
we will fail but we cannot assume the impossibility of success before we try.
Many philosophers and scientists also think that the subjectivity of conscious states makes it impossible to have a strict science of consciousness. For, they argue, if science is by definition objective, and consciousness is by definition subjective, it follows that there cannot be a science of consciousness. This argument is fallacious. It commits the fallacy of ambiguity over the terms objective and subjective. Here is the ambiguity: We need to distinguish two different senses of the objective-subjective distinction. In one sense, the epistemic sense("epistemic" here means having to do with knowledge)
,science is indeed objective
. Scientists seek truths that are equally accessible to any competent observer and that are independent of the feelings and attitudes of the experimenters in question. An example of anepistemically
objective claim would be "Bill Clinton weighs 210 pounds".
An example of anepistemically
subjective claim would be "Bill Clinton is a good president".
The first is objective because its truth or falsity issettleable
in a way that is independent of the feelings and attitudes of the investigators. The second is subjective because it is not sosettleable
.But
there is another sense of the objective-subjective distinction, and that is the ontological sense ("ontological" here means having to do with existence). Some entities, such as pains, tickles, and itches, have a subjective mode of existence, in the sense that they exist only as experienced by a conscious subject. Others, such as mountains,molecules
and tectonic plates have an objective mode of existence, in the sense that their existence does not depend on any consciousness. The point of making this distinction is to call attention to the fact that the scientific requirement of epistemic objectivity does not preclude ontological subjectivity as a domain of investigation. There is no reason whatever why we cannot have an objective science of pain, even though pains only exist when they are felt by conscious agents. The ontological subjectivity of the feeling of pain does not preclude anepistemically
objective science of pain. Though many philosophers and neuroscientists are reluctant to think of subjectivity as a proper domain of scientific investigation, in actual practice, we work on it all the time. Any neurology textbook will contain extensive discussions of the etiology and treatment of such ontologically subjective states as pains and anxieties.