• Start
  • Previous
  • 15 /
  • Next
  • End
  •  
  • Download HTML
  • Download Word
  • Download PDF
  • visits: 6625 / Download: 3138
Size Size Size
Islamic Philosophy and the Problem of Evil; A Philosophical Theodicy

Islamic Philosophy and the Problem of Evil; A Philosophical Theodicy

Author:
Publisher: www.eijh.modares.ac.ir
English

This book is corrected and edited by Al-Hassanain (p) Institue for Islamic Heritage and Thought


Note:

This book was  an article initially, but when we studied it, we preferred to present it in a book form for better usage!
 

Intl. J. Humanities (2010) Vol. 17 (1): (127-148)

Islamic Philosophy and the Problem of Evil; A Philosophical Theodicy

Mohammad Saeedimehr1

Table of Contents     

Abstract 3

Introduction. 4

a) The Theoretical Problem. 4

b) The Existential Problem. 4

c) The Practical Problem. 4

The Reality of Evil 6

Several Versions of the Problem. 7

What is an Evil Like?. 10

Evil as Nonexistence and Privation. 11

Essential and Accidental Evil 13

Several Applications of the Word "Evil"  14

I. To claim that TNNE is self-evident 15

2. To explore several types of evil 15

3. To present a deductive argument 15

Apprehensional Evil: a challenge for TNNE  17

Response to the Challenge 17

Solutions of the Problem of Evil 20

The Negative Nature of Evils 20

The Minor Evil is Necessary for the Major 20

The best possible world. 23

Evils and Reasonable Ends 24

Conclusion. 25

References: 26

Notes 27

Abstract

During the last centuries, great religious traditions as well as prominent philosophical and theological schools have been facing the so-called "problem of evil" and trying to solve it in a reasonable and convincing way. This paper seeks to explore Muslim philosophers' approach to the problem and examine their proposed solutions for it. After the main versions of the problem in Islamic philosophy are briefly sketched, the author explains its view about the non-existential nature of evil. At this stage, he discusses the challenge of "apprehensional evil" and three reactions to it. Then he turns to three main solutions proposed by Muslim philosophers in order to meet three versions of the problem of evil, i.e., the problem of evils and God's decree, the problem of creation-dualism and the problem of evils and Divine wisdom.

Keywords: Evil, God's decree, God's wisdom, Islamic philosophy, Avicenna, Mulla Sadra.

Introduction

The so-called "problem of evil", in its various forms and versions, has a long and impressive history. During past centuries, all great religious traditions – including Abrahamic ones, i.e. Judaism, Christianity and Islam - as well as Hinduism and Buddhism have more or less addressed this problem and tried to propose solutions for it. Moreover, philosophers belonging to different philosophical schools have made valuable attempts to find theoretical solutions. It would be helpful here to note that we can distinguish, from a very general perspective, between three main kinds of what may be called "the problem of evil":2

a) The Theoretical Problem

The theoretical problem of evil concerns the logical relations among certain beliefs about God and His attributes, on the one hand, and the reality of various on the other. One question here, for example, would arise as how could the reality of some actual evils be consistent with Divine justice or wisdom.

b) The Existential Problem

This problem, in contrast with the theoretical one, deals not merely with internal logical relations among a collection of beliefs or statements, but rather with one's personal experience of evils in the actual life which may be highly effective on his/her approach to life and its meaning. For instance, it is possible for someone who is unable to solve the existential problem to loose his/her trust in God or his/her belief in the meaningfulness of life.

c) The Practical Problem

This kind of problem consists of finding a practical way to decrease the amount of actual threatening evils around us and prevent their consequent calamities and disasters as much as possible. We may say that nowadays many charitable institutions are dealing with this practical problem.

Undoubledly dealing with the existential and practical problems of evil actually requires more or less some basic ideas and theories about God, world and Human beings and their interrelations. But a part of these ideas and theories could be presuppositions supported by authorities such as religious scriptures or reliable human information sources. Regarding the very complicated nature of theoretical problem of evil, however, engaging with it requires much more! Thus, we find prominent and well-known philosophers and theologians (among other thinkers) who have undertaken to wrestle, theoretically, with this powerful and nimble competitor!

In this paper, I shall explore briefly the main views of Muslim philosophers on the theoretical problem of evil. Since, there are naturally some disagreements among these philosophers, I, due to some actual limits, should almost restrict myself to the more common views in order to draw a whole and, as far as possible, clear and comprehensive picture that could be, though approximately, attributed to what is usually called "Islamic Philosophy". It is not necessary to mention here that a comprehensive critical and detailed discussion of the issue goes beyond the limits of an article like this.3

Broadly, we may call any approach to solve the theoretical theistic problem of evil a "theodicy". Therefore, the present article seeks to provide a brief exploration of Muslim philosophers' theodicy.4

The Reality of Evil

Before considering the different versions of the problem of evil, it would be helpful to say something about the Islamic philosophy's view on the reality of evils. Confronting the apparent evils around us, one may primarily raise the question whether these evils are real things or they are mere illusions. Contrary to an uncommon view (sometimes attributed to certain Hindu schools of thought) which considers evils as mere dreams and illusions, most people including philosophers and theologians follow their common sense judgment and endorse the reality of evils. It is clear that according to the former view, the problem of evil (if it can be formulated at all) will find a very trite and commonplace solution: the so-called evils are just in our dreams and not real!

Muslim philosophers, however, do not deny that there are really some evils. And thus, considering the other facts concerning God and His attributes, the problem of evil emerges for them as a genuine philosophical problem.

Several Versions of the Problem

In fact, what we called the "theoretical problem" can be expressed in several ways.

According to a contemporary point of view, the main versions of the problem are two: "logical problem of evil" and "evidential problem of evil".5 This distinction, however, has not been common among Muslim philosophers up to now. Indeed, we may hardly be able to find any similar distinction in their works. The main section where they discuss the problem is that which deals with God's attributes and actions.

Many of Muslim philosophers begin their discussion on evil with a consideration of the property of Divine providence. By this property, they usually mean a composition of three attributes: God's knowledge of the best possible order of the universe, His being its actual effective cause and, finally, His being satisfied with its actual realization.

Avicenna puts this definition in this way:

It must, hence, be known that providence consists in the First's knowing in Himself [the mode] of existence of the order of the good, in His being, in Himself, a cause of goodness and perfection in terms of what is possible, and in His being satisfied [with the order of the good] in the manner that has been mentioned. He would thus intellectually apprehend the order of the good in the highest possible manner, whereby what He intellectually apprehends in the highest possible way as an order and a good would overflow from Him in the manner, within the realm of possibility that is most complete in being conductive in order. (Avicenna, 2005, p.339)

However, according to this characterization, Divine providence apparently would imply that our actual world must be of the best possible order. Borrowing Leibniz' terminology, we may say that, given the Divine providence, our world must be the "best possible world". The best possible world, however, seems to be necessarily void of any kind of evils, since we surely maintain that such a world has a better order than that of a world containing evils. So, regarding the reality of evil in our actual world, the theoretical problem arises: How can one who believes in God and His providence (in the above sense) give reason for the actual evils in the world? How can one reconcile between these beliefs: the belief that God is aware of the best order of the world and causes it and is satisfied with it, on the one hand, and that evils are real, on the other hand?

The above questions are commonly expressed by Muslim philosophers appealing to the notion of Divine decree (al-qadha al-ilahi ) and predetermination (al-taqdir al-ilahi ). We should notice that in Muslim philosophers' worldview, the existence of any actual being or the occurrence of any actual event, in the whole universe and in all times, is decided and appointed by Divine eternal decree. In other words, God, as the ultimate (or more accurately, the unique real) efficient cause, necessitates the existence and the occurrence of all actual beings and events. Moreover, all the characteristics and properties of God's creatures are eternally predetermined by God. Thus, if evils are to be real entities, their very realization must be according to the Divine decree and their characteristics must be according to

His predetermination. Therefore, the main question could be expressed as: How do evils come to be according to Divine decree and predetermination?6

We find most Muslim Philosophers deal with the problem of evil under a main title which contains terms such as "Divine providence", "Divine decree" and "Divine predetermination".7

We may then count the above version of the problem as the main version for Islamic philosophers. Let us call it "the problem of evil and Divine providence". The general attempt to solve this problem has been manifested in the attempt to show that evils, in contrast to the goods, are decided and predetermined by God only accidentally and not essentially (I shall return to this solution later).

There are, however, some less important versions of the problem that have been formulated in a much less detailed way of which we rarely cannot find more than some implicit allusions. One of these subordinate versions relates to the problem of the creator of evils. According to Islamic philosophy, and Islamic doctrines in general, God is the most conceivable good and benevolent being. So, how could it be the case that such a God creates evils (pains, sufferings, harms and so on)? If God does not create the evils, then there must be another being (perhaps a cosmic devil) who is responsible for bringing the evils into existence. According to Islamic philosophy, however, this could not be the case, since, God is the ultimate creator of all things so that no other being can be conceived of who is able to create something despite of or against God's will and decision. We may call this problem "the creation-dualism problem".8 As we shall see, Muslim philosophers' key solution for this problem is based on a negative interpretation of the very nature of evils.

Another variation of the problem of evil, which deserves to be mentioned here, originates from Muslim Philosophers' belief in God's absolute wisdom (al-hikmat al-ilahiyyah).

"Wisdom" signifies more than one meaning:

from one aspect, It says something about God's knowledge and insists on its being totally comprehensive and absolutely perfect.

Moreover, wisdom sometimes is applied to Divine actions; God is wise (hakim) in the sense that His actions are perfect as well as reasonable. Avicenna interprets Divine wisdom as follows:

Wisdom, in our opinion applies to two things: to complete knowledge and to perfect action. (Morewedge, 1973, p. 70)

Indeed, the second sense is what we are concerned with here. One may claim that (at least some kinds of) actual evils, if seen as God's actions, are neither perfect nor reasonable. (To be "reasonable", when used as a property of actions, should be understood as having reasonable purposes and goals). For example, natural evils (like earthquakes) are apparently the result of some disorders and imperfect designs in the world. Moreover, one may think that evils like diseases and pains of the innocent creatures could not result in any rational objective.9

Therefore, we confront another problem: It seems that the reality of evils in our actual world contradicts Divine wisdom since they are manifestations of disorder and chaos, from one hand, and vainness and futility, from

another hand, while God's wisdom requires all His actions to be the most perfect and to have reasonable goals and objectives.

What is an Evil Like?

To present a more or less minute definition for "evil" is not as easy as it may seem at the first glance. That is partly because the word "evil", within an Aristotelian metaphysical framework, does not refer to a certain kind of a particular metaphysical category, as "red" or "cat" denotes a certain kind of color or animal respectively.

We may rightly regard things belonging to different categories as "evil". Some of human acts are called "evil" as well as some natural events such as earthquakes and floods.

Moreover, mental states like pain and suffering provide another sort of evils. So, one may wonder whether there could be a single and general concept of evilness applicable to theseheterogeneous entities.

To engage in a fruitful philosophical discussion of the problem of evil, however, it is necessary to have an almost clear conception of what evil is like. Otherwise, it would be too optimistic to expect a satisfying settlement for the problem.

Bearing these facts in mind, Muslim philosophers commonly try to characterize "evil" especially in terms of the opposition between the concepts of good and evil. A conspicuous view is that good consists in (or stems from) existence (wujud ) and, therefore, evil consists in (or stems from) nonexistence (adam ). The immediate result of this view is that all of the various forms and kinds of evil could be reduced to nonexistence and privation; evils, in their very essences, are of negative and non-existential nature. As we shall see later, this type of characterization mobilized Muslim philosophers with a theoretical apparatus, which enabled them to provide a solution for some versions of the problem of evil.

Evil as Nonexistence and Privation

So far I claimed that in Islamic philosophy evils are seen as non-existential entities. But do we in fact see any sort of nonexistence as an evil?

Now that I am writing this paper, there is not a ball on my desk? Then is the nonexistence of a ball on my desk an evil? It seems not. Thus, a kind of modification is required. Some philosophers associate evil with the nonexistence of a (deserved) perfection, which may be called "privation". Al-Farabi, for example, holds:

Indeed, God is nothing but the perfection of existence and it is the Necessary Being (wajib alwujud) and evil is the privation of existence and the negation of perfection. (Al-Farabi, 1408, p. 49)

Avecinna is much more explicit in this respect.

After mentioning some kinds of evil, he says:

Thus, evil in essence is privation, though not any [type] of privation but only privation of that to which the nature of the thing necessarily leads in terms of the perfections that belong permanently to its species and nature. (Avicenna, 2205, p. 340)

So, we do not count any item of nonexistence as an evil but only the lack of such perfection that a thing normally should possess in terms of its nature. Therefore, the lack of sight is an evil for a blind person and not for a tree.

But an existent may be seen as an evil as far as it destroys or prevents another existent's perfection. Avicenna continues to distinguish between essential and accidental evils:

Accidental evil [on the other hand] is the nonexistent, or that which keeps perfection away from that which deserves it. (Ibid)

Avicenna's example to elucidate this distinction is a case in which heat brings about the lost connectedness of one's organ. In this case, in Avicenna's opinion, the essential evil consists in the nonexistence of the connectedness, while the heat itself is an accidental evil, since though "…it becomes an evil relative to the sufferer from it, it has another aspect in terms of which it is not an evil." (Ibid) I shall return to this issue later.

According to Mulla Sadra, however, "evil"

can be used in two senses:

1) In the first sense, all beings except God possess some evil aspects. God, as the unique Necessary Being, is the absolute good and other beings, since they are contingent, can be described as evils as far as they lack the degree of absolute good. In other words, all God's creatures are evils in the sense that they are more or less imperfect. (Mulla Sadra, 1981, p.58) 10

However, Mulla Sadra reminds us very soon that this is not the sense which is usually meant in the philosophical discussions on evil.11

2) Evil, in the second sense, "… consists in the nonexistence of an object or the nonexistence of one of its perfections which is peculiar to it inasmuch as it is that certain object…. Therefore, philosophers said that evil lacks any [existent] essence, it is instead a nonexistent entity which consists in either the nonexistence of an object or of its perfection." (Ibid)

This second sense is what Sadra's predecessors had in mind when they talked about evils. We may call this view about the nature of evils "the

theory of the nonexistent nature of evil" (henceforth:TNNE )12 It is fair to note here thatTNNE should never considered as equal to the aforementioned view which says that evils are nothing except dreams and illusions. According toTNNE , evils are real as well as goods but their very natures are nonexistential and negative. Thus, the blindness and ignorance are realities andTNNE 's claim is just that philosophical analysis shows that they are nonexistent realities.

Essential and Accidental Evil

One may plausibly wonder whether, according to TNNE, beings have any role in the realization of evils. The answer can be affirmative in the sense that we may call some beings "evil" in as much as they bring about the reality of certain evils. In order to distinguish this sense from the non-existential (negative) meaning, Muslim philosophers typically call the former "accidental evil" (al-shar al-bithat) and the latter "essential evil" (al-shar al-bilaradh).

It is helpful to note that "accidental" here should be taken to mean "figuratively" or "metaphorically".13 So, we may admit that some beings could be called "evil" so far as they actually cause some sorts of nonexistence and privation.

Several Applications of the Word "Evil"

Beside the attempt to clarify the non-existential nature of evil, Muslim philosophers commonly explore the different applications of the term "evil". Taking these various uses into account helps us to have a better understanding of what an evil is like and prepares the way for distinguishing several aspects of the problem of evil in correspondence to several types of evils.14

Avicenna distinguishes between four uses of "evil":

Evil is spoken of in [various] ways. Thus "evil" is said of the blameworthy acts, and "evil"

is said of their principles in moral dispositions.

"Evil" is said of pains, distresses, and their like.

"Evil" is [also] said of the falling short by each thing of its perfection and of its loss of that which would naturally belong to it. (Avicenna, 2005, p 343)

According to the above passage, "evil" is applied to four categories:

1. the immoral actions and wrong doings.

2. the principles of these actions in the agent's dispositions.

3. the pains and distresses and like.

4. the lack of an expected perfection.

One may wonder whether the above classification is in accordance toTNNE , since the first three categories in the list obviously are of an existential nature. Facing this problem, Avicenna makes some more analyses in order to disclose the hidden relation of those categories, the nonexistence. He thus goes on to claim that the third class, i.e., the sufferings and pains, "even though their meanings are existential, not privative, follow [from] to privation and deficiency." (Ibid) Therefore, suffering and pains are called evil just as far as they are the result of some privation. (I shall discuss this view later under the title of "Apprehension Evil").

What about the first and second types? Their connection to nonexistence is stated as follows:

Evil in acts is also [evil] in relation to the one who loses his perfection by its reaching him, as with injustice, or in relation to a perfection necessary in the religious regime, as [when] adultery [takes place]. Similarly, moral dispositions are only evil by virtue [of such acts] proceeding from them. And they are connected with depriving the soul of perfection that ought to belong to it. (Ibid)

To sum up, we can say that several categories which normally are called evil are either non-existence and privation (as the lack of the deserved perfection) or originate somehow from nonexistence (like the pains) or bring about some privation whether directly (like malefic actions) or indirectly (like the vices and immoral dispositions). So, we find that in all these various categories, what originally should be considered as evil is nothing but nonexistence and privation.

The Grounds ofTNNE How are the adherents ofTNNE to justify their belief? In the works of Muslim philosophers, we may distinguish three different approaches:

I. To claim that TNNE is self-evident

Mulla Sadra expresses this claim in the following passage: "There is no doubt that existence is, in itself, good and glory and nonexistence is, in itself, evil. And this is the judgment of the primordial nature." (Mulla Sadra, 1990a, p. 121)15

It is helpful to notice that if we accept this claim we should consider philosophers' exploration and analysis of several types of evil to disclose its non-existential nature as mere admonitions (tanbihat) and reminders. This is because Muslim philosophers commonly maintain the possibility of some evident proposition being obscure for some people (due to certain reasons). In this case some reminders and admonitions may be required in order to make the proposition acceptable.

However, it seems that most of Muslim philosophers were not ready to confine themselves to this claim and thus tried to provide some further grounds.

2. To explore several types of evil

The second way is to explore several types of evils in order to show that in all cases the essential evil is a kind of privation (We considered one example of this approach in Avicenna). This approach sometimes has been considered as an attempt to present a kind of inductive argument.

This interpretation, however, has raised an objection based on the weak logical status of induction: inductive arguments are not logically valid arguments and thus, can not result in certain conclusions. Therefore, no inductive argument can conclusively provide adequate support forTNNE .

Fakhr al-Din al-Razi, for example, puts his objection in this way:

This [i.e., to justifyTNNE on the basis of exploring several types or instances of evils] is to rely on just a few examples and you have known that this does not cause any certainty. (Al-Razi and al-Tusi, 1404, part 2, p. 80).

It is clear that this objection is based on the aforementioned interpretation. But we may interpret their project just as an attempt to provide some evidences forTNNE and to answer some possible alleged counterexamples.

Mulla Sadra, after examining the nature of several types of evil such as immoral dispositions and actions as well as some physical evils such as extreme heat and frigidity, puts his defense of this approach in a clear way:

The objective of mentioning these examples is not to argue for this claim by means of induction or analogy, but to answer the counterexamples and clarify the distinction between essential and accidental evils and abolish the confusion between these two and reveal that evilness in all things seen as evil refers to or originates from a non-existential aspect. (Mulla sadra, 1981, p. 62)

3. To present a deductive argument

There is no doubt that the main ground forTNNE , if any at all, could be a deductive argument. Philosophers who adopted this approach proposed different formulations some of which are more complicated than others.16

Mulla Sadra's argument, though long and almost complicated, deserves to be cited in detail:

And the argument is that if evil was an existential entity, it would be evil either for itself or for another object. [But] it is impossible for it to be evil for itself since otherwise it couldn't have existence at all because the existence of an object cannot require its nonexistence or privation of one of its perfections. And if an object requires the privation of some of its perfections, the [real] evil will consist in that privation and not that very object…. And it is also impossible for an evil, given that it is existent, to be evil for another being since it would be evil either because it obliterates that object or obliterates one of its perfections or does not obliterate anything. So, if it is evil because it obliterates that object or one of its perfections, then the evil is nothing but the nonexistence of that object or the privation of its perfection and not that existential entity itself. And if it does not obliterate anything, then it will not be an evil for that object since we certainly know that whatever does not cause the nonexistence of an object, nor the privation of its perfection could not be regarded an evil for that object since that object is not harmed or damaged by it. (Mulla Sadra, 1981, pp. 58-59) 17

In order to criticize this argument I need a broad space. In short, one may say that it commits the fallacy of begging the question for in some stages Sadra proceeds in a manner as if he already has presupposed a non-existential nature for evils. For example, he says that it is impossible for an object to be evil for itself since "the existence of an object cannot require its nonexistence or privation of one of its perfections." It seems that this requirement itself is based on an assumption about evil being necessarily linked to some kinds of nonexistence, but this assumption is what the argument seeks to establish. If this objection is applicable here, then we may conclude that the argument is nothing but a detailed pseudoargument which reveals one's intuition about the non-existential nature of evils.

Apprehensional Evil: a challenge for TNNE

So far we saw that Muslim philosophers generally endorsedTNNE and tried to provide on behalf of it some intuitional, evidential and philosophical grounds. It seems that according to some philosophical principles (almost accepted by them) a certain type of evils, namely pain and suffering, can challengeTNNE in a serious and considerable way. Given that pain and suffering are real evils, many philosophers find that they are certain kinds of apprehension (idrak) and knowledge (ilm) (in its broad sense). For example, Avicenna writes:

Surely, pleasure is the apprehension of the realization of something which counts perfection for the apprehender inasmuch as it is perfection and good. And pain is the apprehension of the realization of something which is calamity and evil for the apprehender inasmuch as it is so. (Avicenna, 1403, p. 337)

Moreover, Muslim philosophers commonly think that apprehension is an existential quality.

Therefore, we apparently discover an obvious counterexample forTNNE ; pains and sufferings are evils which have existential nature! In other words, there is an essential difference between pains and sufferings, on the one hand, and, evils like blindness and diseases, on the other. The former, in contrary to the latter, are not mere privations, but as mental qualities they are as existent as other qualities. Let's call the evils in question "apprehensional evil".18

Regarding the previous distinction between essential and accidental evil, this challenge, in order to be a serious one, should presuppose that apprehensional evil is an essential evil since, as we saw, there is no problem to call some beings "accidental evils" inasmuch as they cause some kinds of privation. Thus, we may formulate the "apprehensional evil challenge" (henceforth: AEC) as follows: (for the sake of simplicity, I restrict myself to the case of pain):

1. Pain is an evil.

2. Pain is an essential evil, not an accidental evil.

3. Pain is a kind of apprehension.

4. All kinds of apprehension are existential entities.

5. Pain is an existential entity. [from (3) and (4)]

6. Therefore, there are essential evils which are existential entities. [the conclusion: from (2) and (5)]

But this conclusion obviously contradictsTNNE .

Some philosophers, like Fackr Al-Din Al-Razi and Mulla Jalal Al-Din Al-Dawani, have objectedTNNE by means of AEC. Al-Razi puts the challenge shortly and in conclusive voice:

It is self-evident that pain is an existential entity and there is no disagreement among wise people about this. (Al_Razi and al-Tusi, 1404, Part 2, p. 80)

The adherents ofTNNE meet this challenge in several ways.

Response to the Challenge

We may classify the main responses to AEC into three types:

I) Some philosophers reject the premise (2) which says that pain is an essential evil. Al-Tusi, for instance, says:

And the case is similar with the pains, since they are not evils inasmuch as they are apprehensions of things or in terms of their existence in themselves or their coming into existence by their causes. Instead, they are evils just in relation to the person who is in pain and lacks the connectedness of an organ which deserves connectedness. (Avicenna, 1404, p. 331)

According to a passage cited before, it seems that Avicenna supports this view when he suggests that pains, "even though their meanings are existential, not privative, follow [from] to privation and deficiency." (Avicenna, 2005, 331)19

II) The second response is to reject premise (3); a universal statement which says that all kinds of apprehension are existential entity.

Mulla Sadra's response to AEC, in my opinion, could be viewed as a challenge for (3). He provides a complicated argument its main steps can be formulated in the following way:

1. Pain involves a kind of apprehension which is an item of "Knowledge by presence" (ilm al-hudhuri) and not of acquired knowledge (ilm al-husuli).20

2. In the case of the knowledge by presence, the apprehension is identical with the very object which becomes apprehended.

3. The realization of privation and nonexistence is itself a kind of privation and nonexistence, as the realization of a human being is identical with him.

4. Thus, in the case of pain, the apprehension involved is of the kind of privation and nonexistence.

5. Therefore, pains really have non-existential nature in spite of being a mode of apprehension.

According to this line of argumentation, Mulla Sadra concludes that "the pain as an essential evil is one of instances of nonexistence." (Mulla Sadra, 1981, p. 66)

III) After Mulla Sadra, some of his commentators criticized his argument and provided a third response which seemingly rejects premise (1) of AEC. In their views, pain, though a kind of apprehension and thus an existential entity, is not a real evil. In order to justify this claim, we are invited to contemplate on various benefits of pains for human beings as human beings. For example, suffering from pains helps us to gain some moral virtues such as patience, satisfaction and so on. In other words, this view insists on the distinction between what is really evil and what only does not fit to our bodily desires and dispositions.

Tabatabaii puts this distinction in another way:

The apprehended idea by which someone suffers is not evil or pain inasmuch as one makes oneself by means of it more perfect. And it is an existential entity. But inasmuch as it is a thing in the external world, like the cut of an organ and the disappearance of the connectedness, it is a nonexistent thing and here lies the [real] evil and pain. (Mulla Sadra, 1981, p. 66)

We may summarize Tabatabaii's claim in this way: pain and suffering, in its mental (and internal) realization is an existent entity but not a real evil and in its external realization is evil but a non-existential entity. Consequently, AEC fails.