Introduction
For present purposes “logic” will be understood to mean the subject whose development is described in Kneale & Kneale [1961] and of which a concise history is given in Scholz [1961]. As the terminological discussion at the beginning of the latter reference makes clear, this subject has at different times been known by different names, “analytics” and “organon” and “dialectic”, while inversely the name “logic” has at different times been applied much more broadly and loosely than it will be here. At certain times and in certain places - perhaps especially in Germany from the days of Kant through the days of Hegel - the label has come to be used so very broadly and loosely as to threaten to take in nearly the whole of metaphysics and epistemology. Logic in our sense has often been distinguished from “logic” in other, sometimes unmanageably broad and loose, senses by adding the adjectives “formal” or “deductive”.
The scope of the art and science of logic, once one gets beyond elementary logic of the kind covered in introductory textbooks, is indicated by two other standard references, theHandbooks
of mathematical and philosophical logic, Barwise [1977] and Gabbay & Guenthner [1983-89], though the latter includes also parts that are identified as applications of logic rather than logic proper. The term “philosophical logic” as currently used, for instance, in theJournal of Philosophical Logic
, is a near-synonym for “nonclassical logic”. There is an older use of the term as a near-synonym for “philosophy of language”. This older usage is understandable, since so much of philosophy of language, and notably the distinction between sense and reference, did originally emerge as an adjunct to logical studies; but the older usage seems to be now obsolescent, and will be avoided here.
One side of the question of logic and philosophical methodology is that of the application of logic in philosophy. Since logic has traditionally been regarded as a methodological discipline, it is difficult or impossible to distinguish applications of logicalmethods
from application of logicalresults
, and no effort to maintain such a distinction will be made here. Distinctions and divisions within the topic of applications of logic in philosophy are to be made, rather, on the basis of divisions of logic itself into various branches. Mathematical logic comprises four generally recognized branches: set theory, model theory, recursion theory, and proof theory, to which last constructive mathematics, not in itself really a part of logic but rather of mathematics, is attached as a kind of pendant. Philosophical logic in the relevant sense divides naturally into the study ofextensions
of classical logic, such as modal or temporal or deontic or conditional logics, and the study ofalternatives
to classical logic, such as intuitionistic or quantum or partial or paraconsistent logics: The nonclassical divides naturally into theextra
classical and theanti
classical, though the distinction is not in every case easy to draw unambiguously.
It should not be assumed that “philosophical logic” will inevitably be more philosophically relevant than “mathematical logic”. Through the early modern period logic as such was regarded as a branch of philosophy, but then that was equally the case for physics, and today the situation is quite different: Only a minority of professional logicians are housed in departments of philosophy, and this is true not just of specialists in “mathematical” logic but also of specialists in “philosophical” logic, many of whom are housed in departments either of mathematics or of computer science. Most nonclassical logics were initially introduced by philosophers, and with philosophical motives, but as their study has developed it has come to include the mathematical investigation of “logics” no one has ever advocated as accounts of the cannons governing deductive argumentation, just as geometry has come to include the mathematical study of “geometries” no one has ever seriously advocated as accounts of the structure of the physical space. For computer scientists, the literal truth of such philosophical ideas as may have played a role in motivating the original introduction of one or another logic is never what matters, but rather the heuristic suggestiveness and fruitfulness of such ideas, when taken in a perhaps metaphorical or unintended sense, for this or that technical application. The discussion to follow accordingly will not give special emphasis to philosophical logic merely because it is called “philosophical”.
Rather, the seven branches of logic that have been distinguished - (1) elementary logic, (2) set theory, (3) model theory, (4) recursion theory, (5) proof theory, (6) extraclassical logics, (7) anticlassical logics - will be given roughly equal coverage. As it happens, each of the seven topic areas listed has a somewhat different flavor: The bearing of some branches on philosophy is pervasive, while the bearing of other branches is localized; the influence of some branches on philosophy has been positive, while the influence of other branches has been problematic; the relevance of some branches to philosophy is widely recognized, while the relevance of other branches is less known and imperfectly understood. As a result there is great variation in the nature of the philosophical issues that the involvement of the different branches with philosophy have raised. And as a result the discussion below will be something of a potpourri.
Philosophy of logic is as much to be distinguished from logic proper, including philosophical logic, as history of linguistics is to be distinguished from linguistics proper, including historical linguistics. Another side of the question of logic and philosophical methodology is therefore that of the methodology of philosophy of logic, insofar as it has a methodology of its own, distinct from the methodology of philosophy at large. The first question about special methods peculiar to philosophy of logic as distinguished from other branches of philosophy is simply the question whether there are any such distinctive methods,
There is much to suggest that it ought to be answered in the negative. The scope and limits of philosophy of logic are quite differently understood by different philosophers of logic, as comparison of such classics as Strawson [1952] and Quine [1970], not to mention Haack [1978], soon reveals. But a not-too-controversial list of central topics in present-day philosophy of logic might include the following:Should truth-bearers be taken to be sentence types, or sentence tokens, or propositions; and if the last, are these propositions structureless or structured; and if structured, are they coarse-grained and “Russellian” or fine-grained and “Fregean”? Are logical forms the same as grammatical forms, or perhaps the same as “deep” in contrast to “surface” grammatical forms; and whether or not they are, are they psychologically real, represented somehow in the mind or brain of the reasoner, or are they merely imposed by the analyst in the course of evaluating reasoning? Does the source of logical truth and logical knowledge lie in the meanings of the logical particles or elsewhere; and should that meaning be conceived of as constituted by truth conditions or by rules of use?
Obviously these central questions of philosophy of logic are very closely linked to central questions of philosophy of language and/or philosophy of linguistics. Indeed, they are so closely linked as to make it hard to imagine how there could be methods peculiar to philosophy of logic alone and not relevant also to these or other adjoining fields.
Yet upon further reflection it appears that there is after all at least one special methodological puzzle in philosophy of logic that may be without parallel elsewhere. The problem in question arises in connection with philosophical debates between propopents of anticlassical logics and defenders of classical logic, and it amounts to just this: What logic should be used in evaluating the arguments advanced by adherents of rival logics as to which logic is the right one? It is natural to suspect that both sides would soon become involved in circular reasoning; no doubt one side would be arguing in a vicious circle and the other side in a virtuous one, but still the reasoning would be circular on both sides. The question of how if at all noncircular debate over which is the right logic might be possible is perhaps the most readily identified distinctive methodological problem peculiar to philosophy of logic. It can, however, conveniently be subsumed under the question of the role of anticlassic logics in philosophy, which is already on the list of seven topics for exploration enumerated above.